[go: nahoru, domu]

Jump to content

Sorites paradox: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
No edit summary
No edit summary
 
(584 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Logical paradox from vague predicates}}
{{expert}}
[[File:Tannin heap.jpeg|thumb|The sorites paradox: If a heap is reduced by a single grain at a time, the question is: at what exact point does it cease to be considered a heap?]]
{{importance|date=July 2006}}
The '''sorites paradox''' ({{IPAc-en|s|oʊ|'|r|aɪ|t|iː|z}};<ref>{{cite web |title=Sorites |website=Omnilexica |url=http://www.omnilexica.com/pronunciation/?q=Sorites |access-date=2014-03-14 |archive-date=2018-09-20 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180920125138/https://www.omnilexica.com/pronunciation/?q=Sorites |url-status=dead }}</ref> sometimes known as the '''paradox of the heap''') is a [[paradox]] that results from [[vagueness|vague]] [[Predicate (grammar)|predicates]].<ref name=Allan2009>{{cite book |last=Barker |first=C. |editor-last=Allan |editor-first=Keith |title=Concise Encyclopedia of Semantics |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3_1snsgmqU8C&pg=PA1037 |year=2009 |publisher=Elsevier |isbn=978-0-08-095968-9 |chapter=Vagueness |page=1037}}</ref> A typical formulation involves a heap of [[sand]], from which grains are removed individually. With the assumption that removing a single grain does not cause a heap to not be considered a heap anymore, the paradox is to consider what happens when the process is repeated enough times that only one grain remains: is it still a heap? If not, when did it change from a heap to a non-heap?<ref name=Sorensen2009>{{cite book |last=Sorensen |first=Roy A. |editor1=Jaegwon Kim |editor2-last=Sosa |editor2-first=Ernest |editor3-last=Rosenkrantz |editor3-first=Gary S. |title=A Companion to Metaphysics |chapter=sorites arguments |year=2009 |publisher=[[John Wiley & Sons]] |isbn=978-1-4051-5298-3 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=i7PG-Vk824UC&pg=PA565 |page=565}}</ref>


==The original formulation and variations==
The '''Sorites paradox''' (''σωρός'' (''sōros'') being [[Greek language|Greek]] for "heap" and ''σωρίτης'' (''sōritēs'') the adjective) is a [[paradox]] that arises from [[vagueness|vague]] [[predicate]]s. The '''paradox of the heap''' is an example of this paradox which arises when one considers a heap of [[sand]], from which grains are individually removed. Is it still a "heap" when only one grain remains?
===Paradox of the heap===
The word ''sorites'' ({{lang-grc-gre|[[wiktionary:σωρείτης|σωρείτης]]}}) derives from the Greek word for 'heap' ({{lang-grc-gre|[[wiktionary:σωρός|σωρός]]}}).<ref>{{Cite book|title = An Introduction to Many-Valued and Fuzzy Logic: Semantics, Algebras, and Derivation Systems|last = Bergmann|first = Merrie|publisher =[[Cambridge University Press]]|year = 2008|isbn = 978-0-521-88128-9|location = New York, NY|page = [https://books.google.com/books?id=zEwNfoAZEGoC&pg=PA3 3]}}</ref> The paradox is so named because of its original characterization, attributed to [[Eubulides|Eubulides of Miletus]].<ref>{{Harv|Barnes|1982}}, {{Harv|Burnyeat|1982}}, {{Harv|Williamson|1994}}</ref> The paradox is as follows: consider a [[wikt:heap|heap]] of sand from which [[grain]]s are removed individually. One might construct the argument, using [[premise]]s, as follows:<ref name=Sorensen2009/>


:''{{val|1000000|fmt=commas}} grains of sand is a heap of sand'' (Premise 1)
The problem is essentially one of [[philosophy of language]], wherein terms may be relative and indefined, as opposed to problems in [[mathematics]] - wherein all terms by nature have some definition - even if it is only as a variable. The paradox is a normal aspect of any attempt to insert imprecise terms into mathematical-like logical formula, or likewise to apply logic to concepts which by definition are imprecise as to be undefinable.
:''A heap of sand minus one grain is still a heap.'' (Premise 2)


[[Mathematical induction|Repeated applications]] of Premise 2 (each time starting with one fewer grain) eventually forces one to accept the [[logical consequence|conclusion]] that a heap may be composed of just one grain of sand.<ref>{{Cite journal| doi = 10.1111/j.1467-9205.2004.t01-1-00230.x| title = Why Induction Is No Cure For Baldness| year = 2004| last1 = Dolev | first1 = Y.| journal =[[Philosophical Investigations]]| volume = 27| issue = 4| pages = 328–344 }}</ref>
==Variations of the paradox==
Read (1995) observes that "the argument is itself a heap, or sorites, of steps of ''[[modus ponens]]''":<ref name="Read">Read, Stephen (1995). ''Thinking About Logic'', p.174. Oxford. {{ISBN|019289238X}}.</ref>
===Paradox of the heap===
Consider a heap of sand from which grains are individually removed. One might construct the argument, using [[premise (argument)|premises]], as follows:


:''A large collection of grains of sand makes a heap.'' (Premise 1)
:''{{val|1000000|fmt=commas}} grains is a heap.''
:''A large collection of grains of sand minus one grain makes a heap.'' (Premise 2)
:''If {{val|1000000|fmt=commas}} grains is a heap then {{val|999999|fmt=commas}} grains is a heap.''
:''So {{val|999999|fmt=commas}} grains is a heap.''
:''If {{val|999999|fmt=commas}} grains is a heap then {{val|999998|fmt=commas}} grains is a heap.''
:''So {{val|999998|fmt=commas}} grains is a heap.''
:''If ...''
:''... So {{val|1}} grain is a heap.''


===Variations===
Repeated applications of Premise 2 (each time starting with one less number of grains), eventually forces one to accept the [[conclusion]] that a heap may be composed by just one grain of sand.
[[File:Color gradient illustrating a sorites paradox with labels.png|thumb|Color gradient illustrating a sorites paradox, any adjacent colors being indistinguishable by the human eye]]


{{Quote|Then tension between small changes and big [[causality|consequences]] gives rise to the sorites Paradox...There are many variations...[some of which allow] consideration of the difference between being...(a question of [[fact]]) and seeming...(a question of [[perception]]).<ref name=Allan2009/>}}
On the face of it, there are three ways to avoid this conclusion. One may object to the first premise by denying that a large collection of grains makes a heap (or more generally, by denying that there are heaps). One may object to the second premise by stating that it is not true for all collections of grains that removing one grain from it still makes a heap. Or one may reject the conclusion by insisting that a heap of sand can be composed of just one grain.


Another formulation is to start with a grain of sand, which is clearly not a heap, and then assume that adding a single grain of sand to something that is not a heap does not cause it to become a heap. Inductively, this process can be repeated as much as one wants without ever constructing a heap.<ref name=Allan2009/><ref name=Sorensen2009/> A more natural formulation of this variant is to assume a set of colored chips exists such that two adjacent chips vary in color too little for human eyesight to be able to distinguish between them. Then by induction on this premise, humans would not be able to distinguish between any colors.<ref name=Allan2009/>
The paradox is tricky for philosophers because they must explain why one of the two premises, or the conclusion, is wrong even though they appear to be self-evident.


The removal of one drop from the ocean, will not make it 'not an ocean' (it is still an ocean), but since the volume of water in the ocean is finite, eventually, after enough removals, even a litre of water left is still an ocean.
===A man's height===
An equivalent paradox can be constructed by considering a man who has a height of, say, seven feet. Although removing one inch from his height would still leave him tall, he would not be considered tall if this was repeated until he was four feet high. At what point is he no longer tall?


This paradox can be reconstructed for a variety of predicates, for example, with "tall", "rich", "old", "blue", "bald", and so on. [[Bertrand Russell]] argued that all of natural language, even logical connectives, is vague; moreover, representations of propositions are vague.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Russell |first=Bertrand |author-link=Bertrand Russell|date=June 1923 |title=Vagueness |journal=[[The Australasian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy]] |volume=1 |issue=2 |pages=84–92 |issn=1832-8660 |doi=10.1080/00048402308540623 |url=http://cscs.umich.edu/~crshalizi/Russell/vagueness|access-date=November 18, 2009 }} [[Cosma Shalizi|Shalizi]]'s [http://cscs.umich.edu/~crshalizi/Russell/vagueness/ 1995 etext] is archived [https://web.archive.org/web/20080515181625/http://cscs.umich.edu/~crshalizi/Russell/vagueness/ at archive.org] and [https://web.archive.org/web/20100209042810/http://www.cscs.umich.edu/~crshalizi/Russell/vagueness/ at WebCite].</ref>
== Proposed resolutions==
=== Trivial solutions ===
A trivial solution is to deny that any number of grains will make a heap. In other words, one might say that the word "heap" is meaningless, since the precise conditions under which it can be verified cannot be produced. Taken to an extreme, this may naturally lead to [[mereological nihilism]].


====Continuum fallacy<!--'Continuum fallacy', 'Fallacy of the beard', and 'Line-drawing fallacy' redirect here-->====
Other philosophers, like [[Bertrand Russell]], simply deny that logic works with vague concepts.
The '''continuum fallacy'''<!--boldface per WP:R#PLA--> (also known as the '''fallacy of the beard'''<!--boldface per WP:R#PLA-->,<ref>David Roberts: [http://writing2.richmond.edu/WRITING/wweb/reason2d.html Reasoning: Other Fallacies] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080915072033/http://writing2.richmond.edu/writing/wweb/reason2d.html |date=2008-09-15 }}</ref><ref name=Thouless1953>{{citation |year=1953 |edition=Revised|last1=Thouless|first1=Robert H. |author-link=Robert H. Thouless |title=Straight and Crooked Thinking |place=London |publisher=[[Pan Books]] |url=http://neglectedbooks.com/Straight_and_Crooked_Thinking.pdf|page=61}}</ref> '''line-drawing fallacy'''<!--boldface per WP:R#PLA-->, or '''decision-point fallacy'''<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://global.oup.com/us/companion.websites/9780199856671/student/chapter5/summary/|title=Chapter Summary}}</ref>) is an [[informal fallacy]] related to the sorites paradox. Both fallacies cause one to erroneously reject a [[vagueness|vague]] [[proposition|claim]] simply because it is not as precise as one would like it to be. Vagueness alone does not necessarily imply invalidity. The fallacy is the argument that two states or conditions cannot be considered [[Difference (philosophy)|distinct]] (or do not [[existence|exist]] at all) because between them there exists a [[continuum (theory)|continuum]] of states.


Strictly, the sorites paradox refers to situations where there are many ''discrete'' states (classically between 1 and 1,000,000 grains of sand, hence 1,000,000 possible states), while the continuum fallacy refers to situations where there is (or appears to be) a ''continuum'' of states, such as temperature. Whether any continua exist in the physical world is the classic question of [[atomism]], and while both [[Newtonian physics]] and [[quantum physics]] model the world as continuous, there are some proposals in [[quantum gravity]], such as [[loop quantum gravity]], that suggest that notions of continuous length do not apply at the [[Planck length]], and thus what appear to be continua may simply be as-yet undistinguishable discrete states.
=== Setting a fixed boundary ===
A common first response to the paradox is to call any set of grains, that has more than a certain number of grains in it, a heap. If one were to set the "fixed boundary" at, say, 10,000 grains then one would claim that for fewer than 10,000, it's not a heap; for 10,000 or more, then it is a heap.


For the purpose of the continuum fallacy, one assumes that there is in fact a continuum, though this is generally a minor distinction: in general, any argument against the sorites paradox can also be used against the continuum fallacy. One argument against the fallacy is based on the simple [[counterexample]]: there do exist bald people and people who are not bald. Another argument is that for each degree of change in states, the degree of the condition changes slightly, and these slight changes build up to shift the state from one category to another. For example, perhaps the addition of a grain of rice causes the total group of rice to be "slightly more" of a heap, and enough slight changes will certify the group's heap status – see [[fuzzy logic]].
However, such solutions are philosophically unsatisfactory, as there seems little significance to the difference between 9,999 grains and 10,001 grains. The boundary, wherever it may be set, remains as arbitrary and so its precision is misleading. Nevertheless, just such arbitrarily precise distinctions are often drawn in real world scenarios. For example, examiners will usually pick one score when setting the boundaries between [[exam]] grades. In other scenarios there seems to be a real threshold, such as the [[straw that broke the camel's back]], but in reality an arbitrary choice was at some point made (such as the choice of that particular camel).


==Proposed resolutions==
=== Multi-valued logic ===
===Denying the existence of heaps===
Another approach is to use a multi-valued logic. Instead of two logical states, ''heap'' and ''not-heap'', a three value system can be used, for example ''heap'', ''unsure'' and ''not-heap''.
One may [[Denying the antecedent|object to the first premise]] by denying that {{val|1000000|fmt=commas}} grains of sand makes a heap. But {{val|1000000|fmt=commas}} is just an arbitrary large number, and the argument will apply with any such number. So the response must deny outright that there are such things as heaps. [[Peter Unger]] defends this solution.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Unger |first=Peter |title=There Are No Ordinary Things |journal=[[Synthese]] |year=1979 |volume=41 |issue=2 |pages=117–154 |doi=10.1007/bf00869568 |jstor=20115446|s2cid=46956605 }}</ref> However, [[A.J. Ayer]] repudiated it when presented with it by Unger: "If we regard everything as being composed of atoms, and think of Unger as consisting not of cells but of the atoms which compose the cells, then, as [[David Wiggins]] has pointed out to me, a similar argument could be used to prove that Unger, so far from being non-existent, is identical with everything that there is. We have only to substitute for the premise that the subtraction of one atom from Unger's body never makes any difference to his existence the premise that the addition of one atom to it never makes any difference either."<ref>{{cite book |last1=Ayer |first1=A.J. |title=Perception and identity: Essays presented to A. J. Ayer, With His Replies. |date=1979 |publisher=Cornell University Press. |location=Ithica, NY |page=324}}</ref>


===Setting a fixed boundary===
However, three valued systems do not truly resolve the paradox as there is still a dividing line between ''heap'' and ''unsure'' and also between ''unsure'' and ''not-heap''.
A common first response to the paradox is to term any set of grains that has more than a certain number of grains in it a heap. If one were to define the "fixed boundary" at {{val|10000|fmt=commas}} grains then one would claim that for fewer than {{val|10000|fmt=commas}}, it is not a heap; for {{val|10000|fmt=commas}} or more, then it is a heap.{{sfn|Collins|2018|p=32}}


Collins argues that such solutions are unsatisfactory as there seems little significance to the difference between {{val|9999|fmt=commas}} grains and {{val|10000|fmt=commas}} grains. The boundary, wherever it may be set, remains arbitrary, and so its precision is misleading. It is objectionable on both philosophical and linguistic grounds: the former on account of its arbitrariness and the latter on the ground that it is simply not how natural language is used.{{sfn|Collins|2018|p=35}}
=== Visual Definition of Heap ===
{{unreferenced|date=December2006}}
Another approach is to define a "heap" visually instead of trying to define it by its number of grains. Someone looking at the collection of grains would probably find it difficult to tell if a grain has been removed (until the collection is very small).


===Unknowable boundaries (or [[epistemicism]])===
But this approach has has a few problems. For one, from certain vantage points, the sand pile may be judged to look like a heap, from others, it may not. Even if one considers heap-ness to be a quality strictly dependent upon the area taken up by the pile of sand as it is projected on to the back of our eye (as in, how much of our [[field of view]] does the sand pile take) ''as seen from only one particular vantage point'', one still has the same problem as before, since one needs to define a certain arbitrary threshold from which we separate the heaps from non heaps. This time, the quantity measured is area, not grains of sand.
[[Timothy Williamson]]<ref>{{cite journal |last=Williamson |first=Timothy |title=Inexact Knowledge |journal=Mind |year=1992 |volume=101 |issue=402 |pages=218–242 |jstor=2254332 |doi=10.1093/mind/101.402.217}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last=Williamson |first=Timothy |title=Vagueness and Ignorance |journal=[[Supplementary Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society]] |publisher=[[Aristotelian Society]] |year=1992 |volume=66 |pages=145–162 |jstor=4106976|doi=10.1093/aristoteliansupp/66.1.145 }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Williamson |first=Timothy |author-link=Timothy Williamson |title=Vagueness |year=1994 |publisher=[[Routledge ]]|location=London }}</ref> and Roy Sorensen<ref>{{cite book |last=Sorensen |first=Roy |title=Blindspots |year=1988 |publisher=[[Clarendon Press]] |isbn=9780198249818 }}</ref> claim that there are fixed boundaries but that they are necessarily unknowable.


===Supervaluationism===
Another argument against using human [[perception]] is that what a person sees as a heap depends on whether the mound is being reduced from a definite heap or increased from a non-heap. People, for example, have different responses to [[ambiguous image]]s.
[[Supervaluationism]] is a method for dealing with irreferential [[singular term]]s and [[vagueness]]. It allows one to retain the usual [[tautology (logic)|tautological laws]] even when dealing with undefined truth values.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Fine |first=Kit |title=Vagueness, Truth and Logic |journal=Synthese |date=Apr–May 1975 |volume=30 | number= 3/4|pages=265–300 |doi=10.1007/BF00485047 |jstor=20115033 |s2cid=17544558 |url=http://www.niu.edu/~gpynn/Fine_Vagueness_Truth%26Logic.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150608192009/http://www.niu.edu/~gpynn/Fine_Vagueness_Truth%26Logic.pdf |url-status=dead |archive-date=2015-06-08 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | url=https://ontologievorlesung.files.wordpress.com/2011/11/van-fraassen-gaps-and-singular-terms.pdf | first=Bas C. |last=van Fraassen |author-link=Bas van Fraassen| title=Singular Terms, Truth-Value Gaps, and Free Logic | journal=Journal of Philosophy | volume=63 | number=17 | pages=481–495 | year=1966 | doi=10.2307/2024549 | jstor=2024549}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Kamp |first=Hans |editor-last=Keenan |editor-first=E. |title=Two Theories about Adjectives |year=1975 |pages=123–155 |publisher=Cambridge University Press}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last=Dummett |first=Michael |title=Wang's Paradox |journal=[[Synthese]] |year=1975 |volume=30 |issue=3/4 |pages=301–324 |doi=10.1007/BF00485048 |jstor=20115034 |s2cid=46956702 |url=http://wylieb.com/Philosophy/ElectronicTexts/Transitivity/Dummett1975.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160422061349/http://wylieb.com/Philosophy/ElectronicTexts/Transitivity/Dummett1975.pdf |url-status=dead |archive-date=2016-04-22 }}</ref>
As an example of a proposition about an irreferential singular term, consider the sentence "''[[Pegasus]] likes [[licorice]]''".
Since the name "''Pegasus''" [[failure of reference|fails to refer]], no [[truth value]] can be assigned to the sentence; there is nothing in the myth that would justify any such assignment. However, there are some statements about "''Pegasus''" which have definite truth values nevertheless, such as "''Pegasus likes licorice or Pegasus doesn't like licorice''". This sentence is an instance of the tautology "<math>p \vee \neg p</math>", i.e. the valid schema "''<math>p</math> or not-<math>p</math>''". According to supervaluationism, it should be true regardless of whether or not its components have a truth value.


By admitting sentences without defined truth values, supervaluationism avoids adjacent cases such that ''n'' grains of sand is a heap of sand, but ''n''-1 grains is not;
=== Group consensus ===
for example, "''{{val|1000|fmt=commas}} grains of sand is a heap''" may be considered a border case having no defined truth value. Nevertheless, supervaluationism is able to handle a sentence like "''{{val|1000|fmt=commas}} grains of sand is a heap, or {{val|1000|fmt=commas}} grains of sand is not a heap''" as a tautology, i.e. to assign it the value ''true''.{{citation needed|date=January 2020}}
One can establish the meaning of the word "heap" by appealing to group consensus. This approach claims that a collection of grains is as much a "heap" as the proportion of people in a group who believe it to be so. In other words, the ''[[probability]]'' that any collection is a heap is the [[expected value]] of the distribution of the group's views.

====Mathematical explanation====
Let <math>v</math> be a classical [[valuation (logic)|valuation]] defined on every [[atomic sentence]] of the language <math>L</math>, and let <math>At(x)</math> be the number of distinct atomic sentences in <math>x</math>. Then for every sentence <math>x</math>, at most <math>2^{At(x)}</math> distinct classical valuations can exist. A supervaluation <math>V</math> is a function from sentences to truth values such that, a sentence <math>x</math> is super-true (i.e. <math>V(x) = \text{True}</math>) if and only if <math>v(x) = \text{True}</math> for every classical valuation <math>v</math>; likewise for super-false. Otherwise, <math>V(x)</math> is undefined—i.e. exactly when there are two classical valuations <math>v</math> and <math>v'</math> such that <math>v(x)=\text{True}</math> and <math>v'(x) = \text{False}</math>.

For example, let <math>L \; p</math> be the formal translation of "''Pegasus likes licorice''". Then there are exactly two classical valuations <math>v</math> and <math>v'</math> on <math>L \; p</math>, viz. <math>v(L \; p) = \text{True}</math> and <math>v'(L \; p) = \text{False}</math>. So <math>L \; p</math> is neither super-true nor super-false. However, the tautology <math>L \; p \lor \lnot L \; p</math> is evaluated to <math>\text{True}</math> by every classical valuation; it is hence super-true. Similarly, the formalization of the above heap proposition <math>H \; 1000</math> is neither super-true nor super-false, but <math>H \; 1000 \lor \lnot H \; 1000</math> is super-true.

===Truth gaps, gluts, and multi-valued logics===
Another method is to use a [[multi-valued logic]]. In this context, the problem is with the [[principle of bivalence]]: the sand is either a heap or is not a heap, without any shades of gray. Instead of two logical states, ''heap'' and ''not-heap'', a three value system can be used, for example ''heap'', ''indeterminate'' and ''not-heap''. A response to this proposed solution is that three valued systems do not truly resolve the paradox as there is still a dividing line between ''heap'' and ''indeterminate'' and also between ''indeterminate'' and ''not-heap''. The third truth-value can be understood either as a ''truth-value gap'' or as a ''truth-value glut''.<ref>{{Cite book | chapter-url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/truth-values/ | title=[[The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]| chapter=Truth Values| publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, [[Stanford University]]| year=2018}}</ref>

Alternatively, [[fuzzy logic]] offers a continuous spectrum of logical states represented in the [[unit interval]] of real numbers [0,1]—it is a many-valued logic with infinitely-many truth-values, and thus the sand transitions gradually from "definitely heap" to "definitely not heap", with shades in the intermediate region. Fuzzy hedges are used to divide the continuum into regions corresponding to classes like ''definitely heap'', ''mostly heap'', ''partly heap'', ''slightly heap'', and ''not heap''.<ref>{{cite q | Q25938993 |last1=Zadeh |first1=L.A. | author-link1 = Lotfi A. Zadeh | | journal = [[Information and Computation|Information and Control]] | doi-access = free }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last=Goguen |first=J. A. |title=The Logic of Inexact Concepts |journal=Synthese |year=1969 |volume=19 |issue=3–4 |pages=325–378 |doi=10.1007/BF00485654 |jstor=20114646 |s2cid=46965639 }}</ref> Though the problem remains of where these borders occur; e.g. at what number of grains sand starts being 'definitely' a heap.

===Hysteresis===
Another method, introduced by Raffman,<ref>{{Cite book | doi=10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199915101.001.0001 |title = Unruly Words: A Study of Vague Language|year = 2014|last1 = Raffman|first1 = Diana|isbn = 9780199915101|publisher=OUP|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=NVfSAQAAQBAJ&pg=PA136|pages=136ff}}</ref> is to use [[hysteresis]], that is, knowledge of what the collection of sand started as. Equivalent amounts of sand may be termed heaps or not based on how they got there. If a large heap (indisputably described as a heap) is diminished slowly, it preserves its "heap status" to a point, even as the actual amount of sand is reduced to a smaller number of grains. For example, {{val|500}} grains is a pile and {{val|1000|fmt=commas}} grains is a heap. There will be an overlap for these states. So if one is reducing it from a heap to a pile, it is a heap going down until {{val|750}}. At that point, one would stop calling it a heap and start calling it a pile. But if one replaces one grain, it would not instantly turn back into a heap. When going up it would remain a pile until {{val|900}} grains. The numbers picked are arbitrary; the point is, that the same amount can be either a heap or a pile depending on what it was before the change. A common use of hysteresis would be the thermostat for air conditioning: the AC is set at 77&nbsp;°F and it then cools the air to just below 77&nbsp;°F, but does not activate again instantly when the air warms to 77.001&nbsp;°F—it waits until almost 78&nbsp;°F, to prevent instant change of state over and over again.<ref>{{Cite journal| doi = 10.1111/j.1467-8284.2005.00558.x |jstor=3329033 | title = How to understand contextualism about vagueness: reply to Stanley| year = 2005| last1 = Raffman | first1 = D.| journal =[[Analysis (journal)|Analysis]]| volume = 65| issue = 287| pages = 244–248 }}</ref>

===Group consensus===
One can establish the meaning of the word "heap" by appealing to [[Consensus decision-making|consensus]]. Williamson, in his epistemic solution to the paradox, assumes that the meaning of vague terms must be determined by group usage.{{sfn|Collins|2018|p=33}} The consensus method typically claims that a collection of grains is as much a "heap" as the proportion of people in a [[social group|group]] who believe it to be so. In other words, the ''[[probability]]'' that any collection is considered a heap is the [[expected value]] of the distribution of the group's opinion.


A group may decide that:
A group may decide that:
*One grain of sand on its own is not a heap
*One grain of sand on its own is not a heap.
*A large collection of grains of sand is a heap.
*A large collection of grains of sand is a heap.


Between the two extremes, individual members of the group may disagree with each other over whether any particular collection can be labelled a "heap". The collection can then not be definitively claimed to be a "heap" or "not a heap", but rather it has a certain probability of being a heap, between [[zero]] and [[unity]].
Between the two extremes, individual members of the group may disagree with each other over whether any particular collection can be labelled a "heap". The collection can then not be definitively claimed to ''be'' a "heap" or "not a heap". This can be considered an appeal to [[descriptive linguistics]] rather than [[prescriptive linguistics]], as it resolves the issue of definition based on how the population uses natural language. Indeed, if a precise prescriptive definition of "heap" is available then the group consensus will always be unanimous and the paradox does not occur.


===Resolutions in utility theory===
The usefulness of this approach is that it tightly defines the meaning of the terms.
{|class="wikitable collapsible" align="right"
|-
! colspan=7 | "''X'' more or equally red than ''Y''"<br>modelled as quasitransitive relation<br>≈ : indistinguishable, > : clearly more red
|-
! {{diagonal split header|<sub>''X''</sub>|<sup>''Y''</sup>}}
! {{color|#f10|f10}}
! {{color|#e20|e20}}
! {{color|#d30|d30}}
! {{color|#c40|c40}}
! {{color|#b50|b50}}
! {{color|#a60|a60}}
|-
! {{color|#f10|f10}}
! ≈
! ≈
! >
! >
! >
! >
|-
! {{color|#e20|e20}}
! ≈
! ≈
! ≈
! >
! >
! >
|-
! {{color|#d30|d30}}
!
! ≈
! ≈
! ≈
! >
! >
|-
! {{color|#c40|c40}}
!
!
! ≈
! ≈
! ≈
! >
|-
! {{color|#b50|b50}}
!
!
!
! ≈
! ≈
! ≈
|-
! {{color|#a60|a60}}
!
!
!
!
! ≈
! ≈
|}


In the economics field of [[utility theory]], the sorites paradox arises when a person's preferences patterns are investigated.
Precise terms have a mechanism by which one can persuade others that a specific application of the term is valid. Vague terms have no such mechanism. If a person insists on calling a seven foot man short, one might suspect that their reference set includes professional [[basketball]] players. Vague terms are useful to the extent that we have consensus, but when used out of context, they risk generating confusion.
As an example by [[Robert Duncan Luce]], it is easy to find a person, say Peggy, who prefers in her coffee 3 [[gram]]s (that is, 1 [[sugar cube|cube]]) of sugar to 15 grams (5 cubes), however, she will usually be indifferent between 3.00 and 3.03 grams, as well as between 3.03 and 3.06 grams, and so on, as well as finally between 14.97 and 15.00 grams.<ref name="Luce.1956">{{cite journal | url=https://www.imbs.uci.edu/files/personnel/luce/pre1990/1956/Luce_Econometrica_1956.pdf | author=Robert Duncan Luce | author-link=Robert Duncan Luce | title=Semiorders and a Theory of Utility Discrimination | journal=Econometrica | volume=24 | number=2 | pages=178–191 | date=Apr 1956 | doi=10.2307/1905751 | jstor=1905751 }} Here: p.179</ref>


Two measures were taken by economists to avoid the sorites paradox in such a setting.
The Sorites paradox merely illustrates logical analysis of how one uses vague language. It indicates that it is a fallacy to assume that everybody agrees on the definition of a vague term. Some people may agree in its application to but not all members of the universe of discourse will as a matter of course. A consensus method essentially changes the definition of a heap from being a [[subjective]] definition to an [[Objectivity (philosophy)|objective]] one.


* [[Comparative (linguistics)|Comparative]], rather than [[positive (linguistics)|positive]], forms of properties are used. The above example deliberately does not make a statement like "Peggy likes a cup of coffee with 3 grams of sugar", or "Peggy does not like a cup of coffee with 15 grams of sugar". Instead, it states "Peggy likes a cup of coffee with 3 grams of sugar more than one with 15 grams of sugar".{{#tag:ref|The comparative form was found in all economics publications investigated so far.<ref name="Armstrong.1948">{{cite journal | url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2226342 | author=Wallace E. Armstrong | title=Uncertainty and the Utility Function | journal=Economic Journal | volume=58 | number=229 | pages=1&ndash;10 | date=Mar 1948 | doi=10.2307/2226342 | jstor=2226342 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/1909554 | author=Peter C. Fishburn | author-link=Peter C. Fishburn |title=Intransitive Individual Indifference and Transitive Majorities | journal=Econometrica | volume=38 | number=3 | pages=482&ndash;489 | date=May 1970 | doi=10.2307/1909554 | jstor=1909554 }}</ref><ref>{{cite report | url=http://econ.haifa.ac.il/~admiller/ArrowWithoutTransitivity.pdf | author1=Alan D. Miller | author2= Shiran Rachmilevitch | title=Arrow's Theorem Without Transitivity | institution=[[University of Haifa]] | type=Working paper | pages=11 | date=Feb 2014 }}</ref> Apparently it is entailed by the object of investigations in utility theory.}}
* Economists distinguish preference ("Peggy likes ... more than ...") from indifference ("Peggy likes ... as much as ... "), and do not consider the latter relation to be [[transitive relation|transitive]].{{#tag:ref|According to Armstrong (1948), indifference ''was'' considered transitive in [[preference theory]],<ref name="Armstrong.1948"/>{{rp|2}} the latter was challenged in 1939 for this very reason,<ref>{{cite journal | url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2224802 | author=Wallace E. Armstrong | title=The Determinateness of the Utility Function | journal=Economic Journal | volume=49 | number=195 | pages=453&ndash;467 | date=Sep 1939 | doi=10.2307/2224802 | jstor=2224802 }}</ref>{{rp|463}} and succeeded by utility theory.}} In the above example, abbreviating "a cup of coffee with x grams of sugar" by "''c''<sub>''x''</sub>", and "Peggy is indifferent between ''c''<sub>''x''</sub> and ''c''<sub>''y''</sub>" as {{nowrap|"''c''<sub>''x''</sub> ≈ ''c''<sub>''y''</sub>",}} the facts {{nowrap|''c''<sub>3.00</sub> ≈ ''c''<sub>3.03</sub>}} and {{nowrap|''c''<sub>3.03</sub> ≈ ''c''<sub>3.06</sub>}} and ... and {{nowrap|''c''<sub>14.97</sub> ≈ ''c''<sub>15.00</sub>}} do not imply {{nowrap|''c''<sub>3.00</sub> ≈ ''c''<sub>15.00</sub>.}}


Several kinds of relations were introduced to describe preference and indifference without running into the sorites paradox.
== See also ==
Luce defined [[semi-order]]s and investigated their mathematical properties;<ref name="Luce.1956"/>
* [[Imprecise language]]
[[Amartya Sen]] performed a similar task for [[quasitransitive relation]]s.<ref>{{cite journal | last=Sen | first=Amartya | author-link=Amartya Sen | title=Quasi-transitivity, rational choice and collective decisions | zbl=0181.47302 | journal=The Review of Economic Studies | volume=36 | issue=3 | pages=381–393 | year=1969 | doi=10.2307/2296434 | jstor=2296434 }}</ref>
* [[Continuum fallacy]]
Abbreviating "Peggy likes ''c''<sub>''x''</sub> more than ''c''<sub>''y''</sub>" as {{nowrap|"''c''<sub>''x''</sub> > ''c''<sub>''y''</sub>",}} and abbreviating {{nowrap|"''c''<sub>''x''</sub> > ''c''<sub>''y''</sub>}} or {{nowrap|''c''<sub>''x''</sub> ≈ ''c''<sub>''y''</sub>"}} by {{nowrap|"''c''<sub>''x''</sub> ≥ ''c''<sub>''y''</sub>",}} it is reasonable that the relation ">" is a semi-order while ≥ is quasitransitive.
* [[Multi-valued logic]]
Conversely, from a given semi-order > the indifference relation ≈ can be reconstructed by defining {{nowrap|''c''<sub>''x''</sub> ≈ ''c''<sub>''y''</sub>}} if neither {{nowrap|''c''<sub>''x''</sub> > ''c''<sub>''y''</sub>}} nor {{nowrap|''c''<sub>''y''</sub> > ''c''<sub>''x''</sub>.}}
* [[Ship of Theseus]]
Similarly, from a given quasitransitive relation ≥ the indifference relation ≈ can be reconstructed by defining {{nowrap|''c''<sub>''x''</sub> ≈ ''c''<sub>''y''</sub>}} if both {{nowrap|''c''<sub>''x''</sub> ≥ ''c''<sub>''y''</sub>}} and {{nowrap|''c''<sub>''y''</sub> ≥ ''c''<sub>''x''</sub>.}}
* [[Coastline paradox]]
These reconstructed ≈ relations are usually not transitive.
* [[Vagueness]]
* [[Fuzzy logic]]
* [[Philosophical Investigations]]


The table to the right shows how the above color example can be modelled as a quasi-transitive relation ≥. Color differences overdone for readability. A color ''X'' is said to be more or equally red than a color ''Y'' if the table cell in row ''X'' and column ''Y'' is not empty. In that case, if it holds a "≈", then ''X'' and ''Y'' look indistinguishably equal, and if it holds a ">", then ''X'' looks clearly more red than ''Y''. The relation ≥ is the disjoint union of the symmetric relation ≈ and the transitive relation >. Using the transitivity of >, the knowledge of both {{color|#f10|f10}} > {{color|#d30|d30}} and {{color|#d30|d30}} > {{color|#b50|b50}} allows one to infer that {{color|#f10|f10}} > {{color|#b50|b50}}. However, since ≥ is not transitive, a "paradoxical" inference like "{{color|#d30|d30}} ≥ {{color|#e20|e20}} and {{color|#e20|e20}} ≥ {{color|#f10|f10}}, hence {{color|#d30|d30}} ≥ {{color|#f10|f10}}" is no longer possible. For the same reason, e.g. "{{color|#d30|d30}} ≈ {{color|#e20|e20}} and {{color|#e20|e20}} ≈ {{color|#f10|f10}}, hence {{color|#d30|d30}} ≈ {{color|#f10|f10}}" is no longer a valid inference. Similarly, to resolve the original heap variation of the paradox with this approach, the relation "''X'' grains are more a heap than ''Y'' grains" could be considered quasitransitive rather than transitive.
== External links ==

==See also==
{{Portal|Philosophy|Psychology}}
{{Div col|colwidth=20em}}
* [[Ambiguity]]
* [[Boiling frog]]
* [[Closed concept]]
* [[Fuzzy concept]]
* [[I know it when I see it]]
* [[Imprecise language]]
* [[List of fallacies]]
* [[Loki's Wager]]
* [[Ring species]]
* [[Ship of Theseus]]
* [[Slippery slope]]
* [[Straw that broke the camel's back]]
{{div col end}}


==References==
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sorites-paradox/ Sorites Paradox]
{{reflist|30em}}
* [http://www.falakros.net/ Falakros Homepage]
* [http://www.blackwell-synergy.com/links/doi/10.1111%2Fj.1467-9205.2004.t01-1-00230.x Sorites Paradox as a Mathematical Puzzle]
* [http://mathworld.wolfram.com/SoritesParadox.html Sorites Paradox at MathWorld]


== References ==
==Bibliography==
{{refbegin}}
*{{Cite book |last=Barnes |first=J. |year=1982 |chapter=Medicine, Experience and Logic |editor1-last=Barnes |editor1-first=J. |editor2-last=Brunschwig |editor2-first=J. |editor3-last=Burnyeat |editor3-first=M. F. |editor4-last=Schofield |editor4-first=M. |title=Science and Speculation |location=Cambridge |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] }}
*{{cite book |last=Black |first=Max |author-link=Max Black |title=Margins of Precision |url=https://archive.org/details/marginsofprecisi00blac |url-access=registration |isbn=978-0-8014-0602-7 |year=1970 |publisher=Cornell University Press |location=Ithaca, NY}}
*{{cite book |last=Burns |first=Linda Claire |title=Vagueness: An Investigation into Natural Languages and the Sorites Paradox |isbn=978-0-7923-1489-9 |year=1991 |publisher=Kluwer Academic Publishers |location=Dordrecht}}
*{{Cite book | first=Myles |last=Burnyeat |author-link=Myles Burnyeat |editor1-last=Schofield |editor1-first=M. |editor2-last=Nussbaum |editor2-first=M. C. |title=Language and Logos |year=1982 |chapter=15. Gods and heaps |location=Cambridge |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] |pages=[https://books.google.com/books?id=M8FjmaH–0V4C&pg=PA315 315–] }}
*{{cite journal |last1=Collins |first1=Rory |title=On the Borders of Vagueness and the Vagueness of Borders |journal=Vassar College Journal of Philosophy |date=2018 |volume=5 |pages=30–44 |url=https://philosophy.vassar.edu/docs/2018-spring-VCJP%20Borders%20w%20CFP.pdf |access-date=21 June 2018}}
*{{Cite book | chapter-url=https://damir.math.uconn.edu/papers/soriteschapter.pdf | doi=10.4324/9780203100806 |title = Qualitative Mathematics for the Social Sciences: Mathematical Models for Research on Cultural Dynamics|isbn = 9780415444828|editor-last1 = Rudolph|editor-first1 = Lee|year = 2013|chapter=The Sorites Paradox: A Behavioral Approach|pages=105–136|first1=Ehtibar N. |last1=Dzhafarov |first2=Damir D. |last2=Dzhafarov}}
*{{cite book |last=Gerla |title=Fuzzy logic: Mathematical Tools for Approximate Reasoning |year=2001 |isbn=978-0-7923-6941-7 |publisher=Kluwer Academic Publishers |location=Dordrecht, Netherlands}}
*{{Cite journal |jstor = 3840922|title = Vagueness and the Sorites Paradox|journal = Philosophical Perspectives|volume = 16|pages = 419–461|last1 = Ludwig|first1 = Kirk|last2 = Ray|first2 = Greg|year = 2002}}
*{{cite conference |first1=Rick |last1=Nouwen |first2=Robert van |last2=Rooij |first3=Uli |last3=Sauerland |first4=Hans-Christian |last4=Schmitz |title=International Workshop on Vagueness in Communication (ViC; held as part of ESSLLI) |publisher=Springer |series=LNAI |volume=6517 |isbn=978-3-642-18445-1 |year=2009|title-link=European Summer School in Logic, Language and Information }}
*{{cite book|editor1-last=Oms |editor1-first=Sergi |editor2-last=Zardini |editor2-first=Elia |title=The Sorites Paradox |year=2019 |publisher=Cambridge University Press }}
*{{cite book|last=Sainsbury |first=R. M. |title=Paradoxes |year=2009 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |edition=3rd}}; Sect.3
{{refend}}


==External links==
* "Margins of Precision" by [[Max Black]]
{{Wiktionary|sorites}}
* Boguslowski
*{{cite SEP |url-id=sorites-paradox |title=Sorites Paradox}} by Dominic Hyde.
* Kit Fine
* Sandra LaFave: [http://lafavephilosophy.x10host.com/open_and_closed_concepts1.htm Open and Closed Concepts and the Continuum Fallacy]
* [[Peter Unger]]


[[Category:Paradoxes]]
{{Paradoxes}}
{{Fallacies}}
{{authority control}}


{{DEFAULTSORT:Sorites Paradox}}
[[de:Paradoxie des Haufens]]
[[Category:Logical paradoxes]]
[[es:Paradoja sorites]]
[[Category:Semantics]]
[[fr:Paradoxes sorites]]
[[Category:Ambiguity]]
[[he:פרדוקס הערימה]]
[[no:Soritesparadokset]]
[[sv:Soritesparadoxen]]

Latest revision as of 21:36, 9 July 2024

The sorites paradox: If a heap is reduced by a single grain at a time, the question is: at what exact point does it cease to be considered a heap?

The sorites paradox (/sˈrtz/;[1] sometimes known as the paradox of the heap) is a paradox that results from vague predicates.[2] A typical formulation involves a heap of sand, from which grains are removed individually. With the assumption that removing a single grain does not cause a heap to not be considered a heap anymore, the paradox is to consider what happens when the process is repeated enough times that only one grain remains: is it still a heap? If not, when did it change from a heap to a non-heap?[3]

The original formulation and variations[edit]

Paradox of the heap[edit]

The word sorites (Greek: σωρείτης) derives from the Greek word for 'heap' (Greek: σωρός).[4] The paradox is so named because of its original characterization, attributed to Eubulides of Miletus.[5] The paradox is as follows: consider a heap of sand from which grains are removed individually. One might construct the argument, using premises, as follows:[3]

1,000,000 grains of sand is a heap of sand (Premise 1)
A heap of sand minus one grain is still a heap. (Premise 2)

Repeated applications of Premise 2 (each time starting with one fewer grain) eventually forces one to accept the conclusion that a heap may be composed of just one grain of sand.[6] Read (1995) observes that "the argument is itself a heap, or sorites, of steps of modus ponens":[7]

1,000,000 grains is a heap.
If 1,000,000 grains is a heap then 999,999 grains is a heap.
So 999,999 grains is a heap.
If 999,999 grains is a heap then 999,998 grains is a heap.
So 999,998 grains is a heap.
If ...
... So 1 grain is a heap.

Variations[edit]

Color gradient illustrating a sorites paradox, any adjacent colors being indistinguishable by the human eye

Then tension between small changes and big consequences gives rise to the sorites Paradox...There are many variations...[some of which allow] consideration of the difference between being...(a question of fact) and seeming...(a question of perception).[2]

Another formulation is to start with a grain of sand, which is clearly not a heap, and then assume that adding a single grain of sand to something that is not a heap does not cause it to become a heap. Inductively, this process can be repeated as much as one wants without ever constructing a heap.[2][3] A more natural formulation of this variant is to assume a set of colored chips exists such that two adjacent chips vary in color too little for human eyesight to be able to distinguish between them. Then by induction on this premise, humans would not be able to distinguish between any colors.[2]

The removal of one drop from the ocean, will not make it 'not an ocean' (it is still an ocean), but since the volume of water in the ocean is finite, eventually, after enough removals, even a litre of water left is still an ocean.

This paradox can be reconstructed for a variety of predicates, for example, with "tall", "rich", "old", "blue", "bald", and so on. Bertrand Russell argued that all of natural language, even logical connectives, is vague; moreover, representations of propositions are vague.[8]

Continuum fallacy[edit]

The continuum fallacy (also known as the fallacy of the beard,[9][10] line-drawing fallacy, or decision-point fallacy[11]) is an informal fallacy related to the sorites paradox. Both fallacies cause one to erroneously reject a vague claim simply because it is not as precise as one would like it to be. Vagueness alone does not necessarily imply invalidity. The fallacy is the argument that two states or conditions cannot be considered distinct (or do not exist at all) because between them there exists a continuum of states.

Strictly, the sorites paradox refers to situations where there are many discrete states (classically between 1 and 1,000,000 grains of sand, hence 1,000,000 possible states), while the continuum fallacy refers to situations where there is (or appears to be) a continuum of states, such as temperature. Whether any continua exist in the physical world is the classic question of atomism, and while both Newtonian physics and quantum physics model the world as continuous, there are some proposals in quantum gravity, such as loop quantum gravity, that suggest that notions of continuous length do not apply at the Planck length, and thus what appear to be continua may simply be as-yet undistinguishable discrete states.

For the purpose of the continuum fallacy, one assumes that there is in fact a continuum, though this is generally a minor distinction: in general, any argument against the sorites paradox can also be used against the continuum fallacy. One argument against the fallacy is based on the simple counterexample: there do exist bald people and people who are not bald. Another argument is that for each degree of change in states, the degree of the condition changes slightly, and these slight changes build up to shift the state from one category to another. For example, perhaps the addition of a grain of rice causes the total group of rice to be "slightly more" of a heap, and enough slight changes will certify the group's heap status – see fuzzy logic.

Proposed resolutions[edit]

Denying the existence of heaps[edit]

One may object to the first premise by denying that 1,000,000 grains of sand makes a heap. But 1,000,000 is just an arbitrary large number, and the argument will apply with any such number. So the response must deny outright that there are such things as heaps. Peter Unger defends this solution.[12] However, A.J. Ayer repudiated it when presented with it by Unger: "If we regard everything as being composed of atoms, and think of Unger as consisting not of cells but of the atoms which compose the cells, then, as David Wiggins has pointed out to me, a similar argument could be used to prove that Unger, so far from being non-existent, is identical with everything that there is. We have only to substitute for the premise that the subtraction of one atom from Unger's body never makes any difference to his existence the premise that the addition of one atom to it never makes any difference either."[13]

Setting a fixed boundary[edit]

A common first response to the paradox is to term any set of grains that has more than a certain number of grains in it a heap. If one were to define the "fixed boundary" at 10,000 grains then one would claim that for fewer than 10,000, it is not a heap; for 10,000 or more, then it is a heap.[14]

Collins argues that such solutions are unsatisfactory as there seems little significance to the difference between 9,999 grains and 10,000 grains. The boundary, wherever it may be set, remains arbitrary, and so its precision is misleading. It is objectionable on both philosophical and linguistic grounds: the former on account of its arbitrariness and the latter on the ground that it is simply not how natural language is used.[15]

Unknowable boundaries (or epistemicism)[edit]

Timothy Williamson[16][17][18] and Roy Sorensen[19] claim that there are fixed boundaries but that they are necessarily unknowable.

Supervaluationism[edit]

Supervaluationism is a method for dealing with irreferential singular terms and vagueness. It allows one to retain the usual tautological laws even when dealing with undefined truth values.[20][21][22][23] As an example of a proposition about an irreferential singular term, consider the sentence "Pegasus likes licorice". Since the name "Pegasus" fails to refer, no truth value can be assigned to the sentence; there is nothing in the myth that would justify any such assignment. However, there are some statements about "Pegasus" which have definite truth values nevertheless, such as "Pegasus likes licorice or Pegasus doesn't like licorice". This sentence is an instance of the tautology "", i.e. the valid schema " or not-". According to supervaluationism, it should be true regardless of whether or not its components have a truth value.

By admitting sentences without defined truth values, supervaluationism avoids adjacent cases such that n grains of sand is a heap of sand, but n-1 grains is not; for example, "1,000 grains of sand is a heap" may be considered a border case having no defined truth value. Nevertheless, supervaluationism is able to handle a sentence like "1,000 grains of sand is a heap, or 1,000 grains of sand is not a heap" as a tautology, i.e. to assign it the value true.[citation needed]

Mathematical explanation[edit]

Let be a classical valuation defined on every atomic sentence of the language , and let be the number of distinct atomic sentences in . Then for every sentence , at most distinct classical valuations can exist. A supervaluation is a function from sentences to truth values such that, a sentence is super-true (i.e. ) if and only if for every classical valuation ; likewise for super-false. Otherwise, is undefined—i.e. exactly when there are two classical valuations and such that and .

For example, let be the formal translation of "Pegasus likes licorice". Then there are exactly two classical valuations and on , viz. and . So is neither super-true nor super-false. However, the tautology is evaluated to by every classical valuation; it is hence super-true. Similarly, the formalization of the above heap proposition is neither super-true nor super-false, but is super-true.

Truth gaps, gluts, and multi-valued logics[edit]

Another method is to use a multi-valued logic. In this context, the problem is with the principle of bivalence: the sand is either a heap or is not a heap, without any shades of gray. Instead of two logical states, heap and not-heap, a three value system can be used, for example heap, indeterminate and not-heap. A response to this proposed solution is that three valued systems do not truly resolve the paradox as there is still a dividing line between heap and indeterminate and also between indeterminate and not-heap. The third truth-value can be understood either as a truth-value gap or as a truth-value glut.[24]

Alternatively, fuzzy logic offers a continuous spectrum of logical states represented in the unit interval of real numbers [0,1]—it is a many-valued logic with infinitely-many truth-values, and thus the sand transitions gradually from "definitely heap" to "definitely not heap", with shades in the intermediate region. Fuzzy hedges are used to divide the continuum into regions corresponding to classes like definitely heap, mostly heap, partly heap, slightly heap, and not heap.[25][26] Though the problem remains of where these borders occur; e.g. at what number of grains sand starts being 'definitely' a heap.

Hysteresis[edit]

Another method, introduced by Raffman,[27] is to use hysteresis, that is, knowledge of what the collection of sand started as. Equivalent amounts of sand may be termed heaps or not based on how they got there. If a large heap (indisputably described as a heap) is diminished slowly, it preserves its "heap status" to a point, even as the actual amount of sand is reduced to a smaller number of grains. For example, 500 grains is a pile and 1,000 grains is a heap. There will be an overlap for these states. So if one is reducing it from a heap to a pile, it is a heap going down until 750. At that point, one would stop calling it a heap and start calling it a pile. But if one replaces one grain, it would not instantly turn back into a heap. When going up it would remain a pile until 900 grains. The numbers picked are arbitrary; the point is, that the same amount can be either a heap or a pile depending on what it was before the change. A common use of hysteresis would be the thermostat for air conditioning: the AC is set at 77 °F and it then cools the air to just below 77 °F, but does not activate again instantly when the air warms to 77.001 °F—it waits until almost 78 °F, to prevent instant change of state over and over again.[28]

Group consensus[edit]

One can establish the meaning of the word "heap" by appealing to consensus. Williamson, in his epistemic solution to the paradox, assumes that the meaning of vague terms must be determined by group usage.[29] The consensus method typically claims that a collection of grains is as much a "heap" as the proportion of people in a group who believe it to be so. In other words, the probability that any collection is considered a heap is the expected value of the distribution of the group's opinion.

A group may decide that:

  • One grain of sand on its own is not a heap.
  • A large collection of grains of sand is a heap.

Between the two extremes, individual members of the group may disagree with each other over whether any particular collection can be labelled a "heap". The collection can then not be definitively claimed to be a "heap" or "not a heap". This can be considered an appeal to descriptive linguistics rather than prescriptive linguistics, as it resolves the issue of definition based on how the population uses natural language. Indeed, if a precise prescriptive definition of "heap" is available then the group consensus will always be unanimous and the paradox does not occur.

Resolutions in utility theory[edit]

"X more or equally red than Y"
modelled as quasitransitive relation
≈ : indistinguishable, > : clearly more red
Y
X
f10 e20 d30 c40 b50 a60
f10 > > > >
e20 > > >
d30 > >
c40 >
b50
a60

In the economics field of utility theory, the sorites paradox arises when a person's preferences patterns are investigated. As an example by Robert Duncan Luce, it is easy to find a person, say Peggy, who prefers in her coffee 3 grams (that is, 1 cube) of sugar to 15 grams (5 cubes), however, she will usually be indifferent between 3.00 and 3.03 grams, as well as between 3.03 and 3.06 grams, and so on, as well as finally between 14.97 and 15.00 grams.[30]

Two measures were taken by economists to avoid the sorites paradox in such a setting.

  • Comparative, rather than positive, forms of properties are used. The above example deliberately does not make a statement like "Peggy likes a cup of coffee with 3 grams of sugar", or "Peggy does not like a cup of coffee with 15 grams of sugar". Instead, it states "Peggy likes a cup of coffee with 3 grams of sugar more than one with 15 grams of sugar".[34]
  • Economists distinguish preference ("Peggy likes ... more than ...") from indifference ("Peggy likes ... as much as ... "), and do not consider the latter relation to be transitive.[36] In the above example, abbreviating "a cup of coffee with x grams of sugar" by "cx", and "Peggy is indifferent between cx and cy" as "cxcy", the facts c3.00c3.03 and c3.03c3.06 and ... and c14.97c15.00 do not imply c3.00c15.00.

Several kinds of relations were introduced to describe preference and indifference without running into the sorites paradox. Luce defined semi-orders and investigated their mathematical properties;[30] Amartya Sen performed a similar task for quasitransitive relations.[37] Abbreviating "Peggy likes cx more than cy" as "cx > cy", and abbreviating "cx > cy or cxcy" by "cxcy", it is reasonable that the relation ">" is a semi-order while ≥ is quasitransitive. Conversely, from a given semi-order > the indifference relation ≈ can be reconstructed by defining cxcy if neither cx > cy nor cy > cx. Similarly, from a given quasitransitive relation ≥ the indifference relation ≈ can be reconstructed by defining cxcy if both cxcy and cycx. These reconstructed ≈ relations are usually not transitive.

The table to the right shows how the above color example can be modelled as a quasi-transitive relation ≥. Color differences overdone for readability. A color X is said to be more or equally red than a color Y if the table cell in row X and column Y is not empty. In that case, if it holds a "≈", then X and Y look indistinguishably equal, and if it holds a ">", then X looks clearly more red than Y. The relation ≥ is the disjoint union of the symmetric relation ≈ and the transitive relation >. Using the transitivity of >, the knowledge of both f10 > d30 and d30 > b50 allows one to infer that f10 > b50. However, since ≥ is not transitive, a "paradoxical" inference like "d30e20 and e20f10, hence d30f10" is no longer possible. For the same reason, e.g. "d30e20 and e20f10, hence d30f10" is no longer a valid inference. Similarly, to resolve the original heap variation of the paradox with this approach, the relation "X grains are more a heap than Y grains" could be considered quasitransitive rather than transitive.

See also[edit]

References[edit]

  1. ^ "Sorites". Omnilexica. Archived from the original on 2018-09-20. Retrieved 2014-03-14.
  2. ^ a b c d Barker, C. (2009). "Vagueness". In Allan, Keith (ed.). Concise Encyclopedia of Semantics. Elsevier. p. 1037. ISBN 978-0-08-095968-9.
  3. ^ a b c Sorensen, Roy A. (2009). "sorites arguments". In Jaegwon Kim; Sosa, Ernest; Rosenkrantz, Gary S. (eds.). A Companion to Metaphysics. John Wiley & Sons. p. 565. ISBN 978-1-4051-5298-3.
  4. ^ Bergmann, Merrie (2008). An Introduction to Many-Valued and Fuzzy Logic: Semantics, Algebras, and Derivation Systems. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. p. 3. ISBN 978-0-521-88128-9.
  5. ^ (Barnes 1982), (Burnyeat 1982), (Williamson 1994)
  6. ^ Dolev, Y. (2004). "Why Induction Is No Cure For Baldness". Philosophical Investigations. 27 (4): 328–344. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9205.2004.t01-1-00230.x.
  7. ^ Read, Stephen (1995). Thinking About Logic, p.174. Oxford. ISBN 019289238X.
  8. ^ Russell, Bertrand (June 1923). "Vagueness". The Australasian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy. 1 (2): 84–92. doi:10.1080/00048402308540623. ISSN 1832-8660. Retrieved November 18, 2009. Shalizi's 1995 etext is archived at archive.org and at WebCite.
  9. ^ David Roberts: Reasoning: Other Fallacies Archived 2008-09-15 at the Wayback Machine
  10. ^ Thouless, Robert H. (1953), Straight and Crooked Thinking (PDF) (Revised ed.), London: Pan Books, p. 61
  11. ^ "Chapter Summary".
  12. ^ Unger, Peter (1979). "There Are No Ordinary Things". Synthese. 41 (2): 117–154. doi:10.1007/bf00869568. JSTOR 20115446. S2CID 46956605.
  13. ^ Ayer, A.J. (1979). Perception and identity: Essays presented to A. J. Ayer, With His Replies. Ithica, NY: Cornell University Press. p. 324.
  14. ^ Collins 2018, p. 32.
  15. ^ Collins 2018, p. 35.
  16. ^ Williamson, Timothy (1992). "Inexact Knowledge". Mind. 101 (402): 218–242. doi:10.1093/mind/101.402.217. JSTOR 2254332.
  17. ^ Williamson, Timothy (1992). "Vagueness and Ignorance". Supplementary Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. 66. Aristotelian Society: 145–162. doi:10.1093/aristoteliansupp/66.1.145. JSTOR 4106976.
  18. ^ Williamson, Timothy (1994). Vagueness. London: Routledge .
  19. ^ Sorensen, Roy (1988). Blindspots. Clarendon Press. ISBN 9780198249818.
  20. ^ Fine, Kit (Apr–May 1975). "Vagueness, Truth and Logic" (PDF). Synthese. 30 (3/4): 265–300. doi:10.1007/BF00485047. JSTOR 20115033. S2CID 17544558. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2015-06-08.
  21. ^ van Fraassen, Bas C. (1966). "Singular Terms, Truth-Value Gaps, and Free Logic" (PDF). Journal of Philosophy. 63 (17): 481–495. doi:10.2307/2024549. JSTOR 2024549.
  22. ^ Kamp, Hans (1975). Keenan, E. (ed.). Two Theories about Adjectives. Cambridge University Press. pp. 123–155.
  23. ^ Dummett, Michael (1975). "Wang's Paradox" (PDF). Synthese. 30 (3/4): 301–324. doi:10.1007/BF00485048. JSTOR 20115034. S2CID 46956702. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-04-22.
  24. ^ "Truth Values". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2018.
  25. ^ Zadeh, L.A. (June 1965). "Fuzzy sets". Information and Control. 8 (3). San Diego: 338–353. doi:10.1016/S0019-9958(65)90241-X. ISSN 0019-9958. Zbl 0139.24606. Wikidata Q25938993.
  26. ^ Goguen, J. A. (1969). "The Logic of Inexact Concepts". Synthese. 19 (3–4): 325–378. doi:10.1007/BF00485654. JSTOR 20114646. S2CID 46965639.
  27. ^ Raffman, Diana (2014). Unruly Words: A Study of Vague Language. OUP. pp. 136ff. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199915101.001.0001. ISBN 9780199915101.
  28. ^ Raffman, D. (2005). "How to understand contextualism about vagueness: reply to Stanley". Analysis. 65 (287): 244–248. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8284.2005.00558.x. JSTOR 3329033.
  29. ^ Collins 2018, p. 33.
  30. ^ a b Robert Duncan Luce (Apr 1956). "Semiorders and a Theory of Utility Discrimination" (PDF). Econometrica. 24 (2): 178–191. doi:10.2307/1905751. JSTOR 1905751. Here: p.179
  31. ^ a b Wallace E. Armstrong (Mar 1948). "Uncertainty and the Utility Function". Economic Journal. 58 (229): 1–10. doi:10.2307/2226342. JSTOR 2226342.
  32. ^ Peter C. Fishburn (May 1970). "Intransitive Individual Indifference and Transitive Majorities". Econometrica. 38 (3): 482–489. doi:10.2307/1909554. JSTOR 1909554.
  33. ^ Alan D. Miller; Shiran Rachmilevitch (Feb 2014). Arrow's Theorem Without Transitivity (PDF) (Working paper). University of Haifa. p. 11.
  34. ^ The comparative form was found in all economics publications investigated so far.[31][32][33] Apparently it is entailed by the object of investigations in utility theory.
  35. ^ Wallace E. Armstrong (Sep 1939). "The Determinateness of the Utility Function". Economic Journal. 49 (195): 453–467. doi:10.2307/2224802. JSTOR 2224802.
  36. ^ According to Armstrong (1948), indifference was considered transitive in preference theory,[31]: 2  the latter was challenged in 1939 for this very reason,[35]: 463  and succeeded by utility theory.
  37. ^ Sen, Amartya (1969). "Quasi-transitivity, rational choice and collective decisions". The Review of Economic Studies. 36 (3): 381–393. doi:10.2307/2296434. JSTOR 2296434. Zbl 0181.47302.

Bibliography[edit]

External links[edit]